1.
The mythology of understanding as something “inner”
As
I discussed in my previous post, a rapid series of modulations brings
us to the topic of understanding when, at the end of §138,
the interlocutor says:
But we understand the meaning
of a word when we hear or say it; we grasp the meaning at a stroke,
and what we grasp in this way is surely something different from the
'use' which is extended in time!
This
is probably the strongest objection so far to Wittgenstein's account
of meaning. Its power stems from the way it ties into various
extremely tempting ideas about the process of communication. Above
all, it suggests that understanding is some kind of thing that
we acquire when we learn the meaning of a word, and which is
subsequently represented to us whenever we hear that word.
The
appeal of this idea is bolstered by various simple reflections. When
we come to know the meaning of a word we gain understanding –
so we must've gained something! Likewise, if we don't know the
meaning of a word then we lack understanding – so
“understanding” must be whatever it is we lack. And although we
might exhibit understanding in performance (eg, by using a word
correctly), that is not understanding itself; it is merely
evidence from which others can infer that we do indeed possess
understanding.
Moreover,
when we hear words we are immediately aware of our understanding. The
words strike us in a quite vivid and particular way. We don't simply
hear sounds or see ink-marks on a page (or shapes on a computer
screen) – we hear (or read) language. We experience
the meanings that it conveys. To see that this is so, just compare
the case of reciting a passage we don't understand (having learnt it
parrot-fashion, perhaps) with that of reciting one whose words are
familiar to us. Surely it is undeniable that what happens inside us
in the two cases is completely different?
Such
considerations present a challenge for Wittgenstein. When we
understand a word we understand its meaning. But what we grasp in the
instant of understanding doesn't seem to be anything like a use.
(And, in any case, is use something that could
be grasped in an instant?) But if what we grasp isn't use then
meaning can't be use.
2.
Pictures and their application
Wittgenstein
begins his assault on this appealing conception by considering the
notion that understanding is a picture
that comes before our mind when we hear a word (§139).
It's a natural enough place to start given that his early philosophy
propounded what's called “the picture theory of language”.
Moreover, that theory was itself a refinement of a venerable
philosophical position dating back at least as far as Locke's Essay
Concerning Human Understanding.
In my last
post I gave a rough sketch of the account of communication that
the picture theory tends to suggest. It might be helpful to repeat
that here:
Person
A has the thought, in the form of a picture, that things are
thus-and-so. She wants to communicate her thought to B so she
“converts” it into a proposition: she speaks, writes, uses
sign-language or Morse code, etc. The words she uses relate to the
elements of her picture and are arranged in a similar fashion. Next,
B perceives A's proposition and he re-converts it into a thought.
That is to say, the words he hears (reads, etc) produce a picture in
his mind. That picture is his understanding of what A said. If he has
the same picture he has understood correctly; if he has a different
picture then he has misunderstood (and if he has no picture at all
then he has not understood at all). The correctness of his picture
can be inferred from his behaviour. Of course, we can't be sure
B's picture matches A's but so long as he fetches the right object
(etc) then it is reasonable to assume that it does.
In
attacking the idea of understanding as a picture, it is this last
part of the account that Wittgenstein focuses upon: the link between
the picture and subsequent behaviour. He points out (§139)
that, whatever might happen in our minds, our behaviour is still a
criterion for understanding. If someone consistently uses
a word incorrectly then we say that he or she doesn't understand its
meaning. So understanding is clearly bound up with use in some sense.
But if understanding is a mental picture then what is the link
between that picture and use? “Can what we grasp at a
stroke agree with a use, fit or
fail to fit it?” (§139.)
Wittgenstein suggests an answer to his own question: let's assume
that when I hear the word “cube” I get a picture of a cube in my
mind. If I point to a cube my use fits the picture, but if I point to a
triangular prism instead then my use has failed to fit the picture.
At
first blush this seems straightforward, but Wittgenstein argues that
it will not do. The problem is: who is to say that pointing to the
triangular prism actually is
an incorrect use of the picture?
His objection is couched in terms of the picture's “method of projection”.
I assume that's a glance back to Wittgenstein's time as an
engineering student and refers to techniques used in technical
drawing. I'm afraid I have roughly zero understanding of such things
(I looked up geometric projection on Wikipedia and it didn't help)
but there are other ways of making the same point. Basically it comes
to this: a picture by itself stands in need of a method of
application. If no method is
stipulated then it's impossible to say whether a picture has been
used rightly or wrongly.
So,
returning to the example of “cube”, the word presents me with a
picture:
I then look about me and spot a triangular prism. I realise that in both cases they have equal ends and parallel rectilinear figures and that their sides are parallelograms. I therefore point to the triangular prism because, in that sense, it is the same as my picture. In other words, I have used my picture as an example of a prism (for a cube is a prism too). That might seem an unusual way of applying the picture, but who is to say that it's wrong?
To
see how far use can deviate from expectation, consider the following
example: I present someone with a dog and an iPhone. I then give him
a photo of the dog and ask him to choose which of the two items it
most resembles. He chooses the iPhone because, like the photo, you
can hold it in your hand, put it in your pocket, etc. Of course most
of us would automatically choose the dog, but that is only because we
are already familiar with the activity of picking things out from
photos. It is something we’ve done countless times and so it
probably wouldn’t even occur to us to use the photo in a different
way. But there is nothing that says choosing the dog must
be the correct response in all circumstances. Indeed to someone with
a different upbringing from ours the dog might seem an absurd
choice.
The
picture, don't forget, is not being cast as an aid
to understanding; it is supposed to be the thing itself.
But it's hard to see how it can play that role when it provides no
standard of correctness. If this observation seems familiar, that's
because it is closely analogous to the point made about ostensive
definition in relation to meaning. There, it was supposed that
the sample by itself
could establish a link between word and object, that it was
completely unambiguous and therefore unmistakable. But it turned out that it
only functioned as part of an established practice of describing the
rule for the use of a
word. And it's a very similar story in the case of the picture (which
is, after all, a kind of mental
sample). We have the sample, but what we lack is the application. (I
should also mention that as well as looking back to ostensive
definition this point also anticipates aspects of the discussion of
rule-following. See, for example, §201:
“if every course of action can be brought into accord with the
rule, then it can also be brought into conflict with it. And so there
would be neither accord nor conflict here”. This overlap should not
be surprising; the concept of understanding is internally connected
to the concept of meaning. Each helps define the other. And they are
both closely bound up with the concept of rule-following.)
3. Compulsion
The
reminder that a picture can be used in various different ways also
serves to highlight (and undermine) another temptation regarding
understanding as an “inner” phenomenon: the assumption that the
relation between representation and what is represented somehow takes
care of itself. We don't need to stipulate a method of application
because the picture does it for us. It's especially easy to think
like this when we focus on the immediacy and fluency with which we
usually understand language. We don't have to struggle to grasp the
meaning – in fact, it's impossible for us not
to understand. It's as if the picture somehow carries its meaning
within it, like a kind of spirit, and exposure to the picture
transfers this spirit to us, so that we cannot help but see the
picture as an image of this
object. The words (or rather the images they produce) force
an application on us (§140).
In
the Tractatus this
seems to be regarded as a kind of logical
compulsion. So long as picture and fact share the same logical
structure there cannot
be doubt about what's represented. Of course, this idea is exploded
by the simple observations in §139
(it is, in fact, another example of a rule
misrepresented as a necessary feature of the world). But there
are other ways of presenting the idea of compulsion. As Wittgenstein
says in §140,
“we might also be inclined to express ourselves like this: we're at
most under a psychological, not a logical, compulsion”. He then
adds a typically cryptic coda: “And now, indeed, it looks as if we
knew of two kinds of case.” What's he getting at here?
I
think this is a warning against defending a preconception by taking
refuge in theoretical explanations. We assumed we were under
compulsion; the idea that it was a logical one has proved empty, so
now we say it must be “some other kind”. And, happily, we hit
upon the notion of “psychological compulsion” as a
plausible-sounding alternative. (Already we can see the bewitching
idea of a mental mechanism
looming on the horizon.) But notice how vague all this is! How much
do we actually know about psychological compulsion? Is it clear
that this is an example of it? And how do we propose to find out?
Will we be conducting field experiments or can we decide things from
our armchairs? Isn't the idea of psychological compulsion just a
guess – and a guess
that invokes a mysterious realm of mental structures, subconscious
computation, and so forth?
There's
a second, perhaps more fundamental, issue. We've been attempting to
clarify the concept of understanding, but now it looks as if we're
sliding into a quasi-causal explanation. But that's like trying to
find out what a watch is
by examining the structure of its cogs and springs. Such an
investigation may be useful in various ways, but it won't tell you
anything about the role watches play in people's lives. For that you
need to describe their use,
not their internal mechanisms. The notion of compulsion tempts us
away from a conceptual investigation towards an ersatz scientific one
which is doomed to failure from the outset.
Well,
Wittgenstein may be alluding
to such thoughts in §140,
but he doesn't elaborate on them at this point. Instead, he sidesteps
the quagmire of compulsion and brings things down to earth: “our
'belief that the picture forced a particular application upon us'
consisted in the fact that only the one case and no other occurred to
us.” This, of course, is a move from the theoretical back to the
descriptive. Why no
other case occurred to us is not Wittgenstein's concern. But the fact
that they didn't made it seem like the picture could only be applied
in one way even though (as we now see) that's not true at all.
It
is this observation that subsequently allows him to answer the
question in §139:
how can what's grasped in an instant fit or fail to fit a use?
“[T]hey can clash in so far as the picture makes us expect a
different use; because people in general apply this
picture like this”
(§141).
What seemed to be a mysterious (perhaps impossible) relation between
two entirely different phenomena turns out to be remarkably simple
and ordinary.
4. Building in the
application
Maybe,
however, compulsion isn't the only answer. Perhaps we could build the
application into the picture itself, thereby allowing it to perform
its allotted function. Wittgenstein considers this in §141.
“How,” he asks, “am I to imagine this?” The answer he
suggests is a picture of two cubes with lines of projection between
them. Something a bit like this perhaps:
Actually, I don't think that quite works. The cube on the left presumably represents the mental image and the one on the right represents actual cubes in the world (and the lines attempt to show the relation between the two). But we no longer have the mental image that the left-cube pictures! So we're going to need two separate images: first, the picture of the cube by itself and, second, the picture of the two cubes showing how the cube in the first picture is to be applied. But this raises a further problem: how do we know the relationship between these two images? How do we know that the left-cube in the second image represents the cube in the first image? Aren't we going to need a third image depicting the relation between the two we already have? And won't that in turn require a fourth and fifth image linking the third image to the first and second ones? And so on.
In
a roundabout way this comes to the same objection that Wittgenstein
makes about his own proposed image: whatever its content it will
still just be another picture, and will therefore stand in need of an
application. It's not simply that the initial picture did
not provide its
application (as if that were a kind of oversight); it could
not do so. Application cannot be
provided in that way.
Is
Wittgenstein claiming, then, that there's no such thing as an
application coming before one's mind? Of course not, but (he reminds
us in §141)
understanding what that
amounts to involves looking at the use of the phrase “the
application came before his mind”. It does not
involve a doomed attempt to posit a hypothetical picture with
miraculous powers. Instead of analysing the phrase himself, however, Wittgenstein leaves it up to us investigate. I think it's worth
having a go because the conclusions it suggests (to me, at any rate)
tie in with many of the points he will shortly be making about other
accounts of understanding. Here's what I came up with:
a. Suppose I've been
teaching someone to use mathematical formulae. Now I show her the
series 0, 1, 1, 2, 3, 5, 8 and ask her to continue it. She ponders
for a while and then cries “I've got it!” I ask her what's
occurred to her and she writes down the formula “Fn = Fn-1 + Fn-2”.
Then she correctly continues the series. That would count, I think,
as an example of the application coming before her mind. Something
occurred to her and it helped her continue the series.
b. However, it would also
count if, instead of the formula, she writes down “Each new number
is the sum of the previous two”. So what comes before her mind
needn't be one specific thing.
c.
But suppose instead when I show her the series she simply says “Oh,
that's easy!” and correctly continues it: “...13, 21, 34, 55...”.
And when I ask what occurred to her she says “Nothing – it was
obvious.” (Perhaps she's worked through the series numerous times
before.) Here no
application came before her mind; she just knew what to do. In other
words, correct performance by itself is not a sufficient criterion.
Did she understand my
order to continue the series? Yes, but that shows you can understand
something without an
application coming before your mind.
d.
Finally, suppose that she writes down the formula as in the first
example, but then has no idea how to continue the series. It later
transpires that she'd previously seen the formula written below the
series and that's why it occurred to her. Here again the application
has not come before her mind even though what occurs to her – the
formula – is exactly the same as in the first example. So correct
performance might not be sufficient, but it's clearly important.
But
what, then, is the difference between (a) and (d)? From the point of
view of the criteria for the phrase “the application came before
her mind”, the difference is not what's in her mind but her past
experiences: her education, training and so on. The formula only
counts as the application in the right circumstances.
We might sum up all these reflections in the following way: however
you slice it, understanding involves more (and sometimes less) than
an application coming before one's mind.
5. Conclusion
A picture cannot fulfil
the role of understanding by itself. This is not to deny that at
least sometimes a word can bring an image before our minds, nor that
the image might help us to use the word correctly. But it cannot
show that we have used the word correctly; it supplies no
method of application and hence no standard of correctness – and
the criteria for applying the term “understanding” are closely
bound up with correct usage.
However, the appeal of
supposing understanding to be an inner “Something” is not so
easily dispelled. Thus, for example, we might think that (questions
of application aside) the pictorial account of understanding is
implausible simply because it doesn't seem to match what actually
happens. When we hear someone speak we don't get a torrent of
pictures running through our minds one after the other. Yet instead
of making us abandon the idea, this objection typically leads to
attempts at refining it. We might wonder, for example, if the
pictures are somehow unnoticed. Do they go by too fast? Are they
perhaps unconscious? And need they be conventional images at
all? Mightn't they take a form that we wouldn't easily recognise as
pictures – formulae, for example? Now comes the thought that what
we're really talking about is something that allows us to compute
the correct output for a given input. And if that's the case, then
isn't “understanding” a question of having the right mental
structure – one that facilitates correct responses? And need
this structure actually be mental? Couldn't it be a state of
the brain? And so on.
It is these types of
“refinement” that Wittgenstein considers in the remaining
sections on understanding. They all, I think, flounder on the point
already made: “understanding” is bound up with application, and
correctness of application can only be given by an established
practice. Nevertheless, it is important for Wittgenstein to
deal with these new variations because otherwise the suspicion will
remain that he has been over-hasty. The prejudice in favour of the
inner “Something” is deep-rooted; digging it out requires tracing
it through all its manifestations. So that's the next post.